Bruce
Ashford, a professor at Southeastern Baptist Theological Seminary,
recently published an article entitled “The (Religious) Problem with Libertarianism”. It was brought to my attention by Tom
Woods, who responded to it in a podcast a couple of days ago.
Mr.
Ashford is a respected theologian and the co-author of a recently
published book entitled “One Nation Under God: A Christian Hope forAmerican Politics.” From what I have read, his theological views
are pretty similar to my own, and his political thought has, like
mine, been strongly influenced by the thought of Abraham Kuyper.
Hence,
when I discovered that he had written an article about
libertarianism, I was interested to read what he had to say, and
decided to write a response. My response differs in approach from
that of Tom Woods. Tom Woods is far more knowledgeable than I am
about libertarianism, history, and economics, and that shows in what
he has to say. My response is based on the fact that I am coming
from pretty much the same theological position as Bruce Ashford.
I
have reprinted his article in full. My response is in blue.
The
(Religious) Problem with Libertarianism
In
the last twenty years, American life has seen the rise of
libertarianism as a force to be reckoned with in American politics,
especially within the Republican Party. Libertarianism is a view that
places an extraordinary emphasis on liberty—as it defines
liberty—and orders society in a particular manner in order to
achieve that liberty.
The
first sentence is fairly uncontroversial. The second has two rather
peculiar phrases: 1) “places an extraordinary emphasis on liberty”
and 2) “as it defines liberty”. The latter is designed to
suggest that libertarianism’s definition of liberty is flawed. The
former - part of Ashford’s definition of libertarianism - is odd in
that he could simply have said “Libertarianism is a view that
regards liberty as so important that society should be ordered in
such a way as to achieve liberty.” Why did he describe the
emphasis as “extraordinary”?
Libertarianism’s
View of Liberty
Libertarianism
elevates liberty to pre-eminent status in politics and public life.
Those who hold this view tend to consider state power as a necessary
evil, and one that should be confined to the functions of protecting
people against harm.
I
would have ended the first sentence after the word ‘politics’.
What does he mean by “public life”? As for the second sentence,
many libertarians consider state power to be unnecessary.
In
The Concise Conservative Encyclopedia, Karl Hess defines
libertarianism thus:
Libertarianism
is the view that each man is the absolute owner of his life, to use
and dispose of as he sees fit; that all social actions should be
voluntary; and respect for every other man’s similar and equal
ownership of life and, by extension, property and fruits of that
life, is the ethical basis of a humane and open society. In this
view, the only function of law or government is to provide the sort
of self-defense against violence that an individual, if he were
powerful enough, would provide for himself.
Indeed,
libertarians argue that government power is justified only to protect
certain negative rights of its citizens, rights such as private
property, privacy, and personal security. Such a limitation of
government’s powers, they argue, enables society to achieve liberty
and justice for all. In fact, justice is simply the outcome in which
free agents voluntarily act within their rights to create the life
they want—to the extent that they are able to do so. Many
libertarians also argue that this view of government and liberty is
the only one that ensures citizens to live meaningfully.
That
all seems fairly uncontroversial.
The
rhetoric and values underpinning libertarianism should sound
familiar. With the extreme emphasis on liberty, one could be forgiven
for confusing it with its estranged cousin, liberalism. Both
ideologies place paramount value on personal liberty. Both see the
government’s role primarily as one of protecting that liberty. But
liberals and libertarians part ways quite early on in the discussion,
because they define liberty so differently.
No
quarrel with that, except that I find the word “extreme” in the
second sentence rather strange.
American
liberals, in their emphasis on liberty, focus on the way traditional
social norms restrict a person’s freedoms. Thus they elevate their
preferred values (most prominently, sexual freedom) and seek to enact
laws that give pride of place to those values. Libertarians, on the
other hand, focus primarily on the way that the state restricts a
person’s freedoms. Consistent libertarians will articulate that
they care little about elevating their pet values; they simply wish
for the state to be as small and unobtrusive as possible.
The
comments about libertarianism strike me as quite fair.
Libertarianism
as False Religion
From
one perspective, libertarianism may be seen as the foil to socialism.
Socialism takes a good and virtuous goal (equality) and stretches it
too far by making it the standard for all of social life.
Libertarianism is guilty of the same stretching, but instead of
equality, the idol of choice is liberty. The fruit of these
ideologies may look different, but the root problem remains the
same—making a good aspect of God’s creation into a functional
god.
I
have two comments on this.
First
of all, I find the comparison between libertarianism and socialism
curious. As a Christian, I see a lot in the Bible that speaks
positively of freedom - and in particular, freedom for believers to
serve God without the interference of the state, (including freedom
of speech for prophets, apostles and evangelists). There is also a
strong current running through the Bible suggesting that rulers
should not use their power to kill people or take their property.
Liberty is a biblical virtue. However, I see nothing at all in the
Bible that suggests that economic equality is a virtuous goal. The
rich are warned about the dangers of wealth, and encouraged to be
generous, but that is very different from saying that economic
equality is a worthy goal.
Secondly,
I cannot see how a political movement making the pursuit of liberty
its main goal is idolatrous, any more than it is idolatrous for a
school to make educational excellence its main goal, or for a
business to make profit its main goal, or a football team to make
winning games its main goal.
Libertarianism
is right to emphasize the importance of liberty and its connection
with a non-intrusive government. As Christians, one of the reasons we
appreciate liberty is that it allows us to worship and act according
to our religious convictions. Abraham Kuyper expresses this well when
he writes, “Can it be denied that the centralizing State grows more
and more into a gigantic monster over against which every citizen is
finally powerless?” The more expansive government becomes, the
more liberties are taken from individuals.
I
completely agree.
And
yet, as John Bolt has shown, libertarianism manifests itself as a
false religion in the instances when it deifies freedom, giving it a
sort of autonomy that God alone should have. Ideological
libertarianism seeks to free us from nearly every conceivable
restriction. The error of liberalism creeps in here, though in a
different guise. Libertarianism, like liberalism, rests on the faulty
foundation of the human autonomous will. It is a manifestation of our
first parents’ tragic sin, a way of saying, “What I want must
reign supreme.”
Bolt
is, no doubt correct that in the instances in which libertarianism
deifies freedom, it has made itself a false religion. But how many
instances are there of that? And what exactly is this 'ideological'
libertarianism that seeks to free us from nearly every conceivable
restriction? Political libertarianism does not seek to free us from
every conceivable restriction. It does not say or imply that “what
I want must reign supreme.” It simply says (broadly speaking) that
the state should not injure people, or seize their property, or
restrict their freedom of speech or their freedom of association.”
In
the place of this sort of autonomous freedom, we as Christians should
seek a different type of liberty. True freedom, according to
Scripture, does not entail removing every possible restriction, but
removing those restrictions that violate our nature as beings made in
God’s image. For example, it is perfectly good for Americans to
achieve a legislative and judicial consensus that taking the life of
unborn babies is wrong (a position that cannot be justified,
according to some libertarians). Our personal freedoms conflict more
often than we realize, and the government must arbitrate those
conflicts to prevent anarchy.
I’m
happy with the first two sentences. The third sentence finishes with
a rather odd parenthetic comment, but other than that, it's fine.
The fourth sentence, however, puzzles me. Do our personal freedoms
really conflict more often than we realize? What does he have in
mind? I suspect that in reality, our personal freedoms rarely
conflict except when one person uses their freedom to defraud, steal
from, or injure other people.
And
in those instances, most libertarians wouldn’t have a major problem
with government arbitrating.
Libertarianism
is also right to make a connection between liberty and justice. They
rightly emphasize that modern nation-states should foster an
environment in which people are free to acquire property, sell
property, have privacy, and be protected from violence that would
undermine those rights and freedoms. However, most libertarians seek
to restrict government’s role so dramatically that it would prevent
the government from achieving other good and legitimate ends.
I,
of course, agree with the first two sentences. When it comes to the
third sentence, I suspect that in the real world, government may
often claim that it will achieve good and legitimate ends, and that
it has indeed done so. But that the truth is that its promises are
usually hollow, and the good things that it boasts of having achieved
would generally have happened without its intervention.
One
such legitimate end is a modest levelling of the social playing
field. Libertarians define justice in terms of “just acquisition of
wealth.” As they see it, if a person has acquired property,
possessions, and financial resources in a way that is legal and
moral, justice has been achieved. In other words, true justice
depends upon autonomous agents being able to keep all the fruits of
their labors. However, the Christian notion of justice does not exist
without a Christian notion of compassion for the poor, which
sometimes means extending aid to those who cannot care for
themselves. After all, when it comes to wealth, we are always liable
to exaggerate our role in acquiring it, and to ignore those who
assisted us in getting there. Not a one of us can truly pull himself
up by his own bootstraps.
I
don’t know what Ashford means by “a modest levelling of the
social playing field”. I also am interested in the implication
that an immodest levelling of the social playing field may not be
legitimate, and wonder just how modest a levelling is legitimate.
Where in the Bible does he get the impression that it is legitimate
for government to level the social playing field - at least modestly?
As for the third sentence, I would quibble. It should read “if a
person has acquired property, possessions, and financial resources in
a way that is legal and moral, no injustice has been committed.”
This is quite different from justice having been achieved. Similarly
the fourth sentence is strange. I, and I suspect most libertarians,
would prefer “True justice does not permit people to have the
legitimately acquired fruits of their labours seized from them.”
And yes, compassion for the poor is part of justice, and it does mean
extending aid to those who cannot care for themselves, but what has
that got to do with the government? I am sure that the apostles
would have thought that it was completely bizarre to think that it
was Caesar’s job to take the money of ordinary people so that he
could give it to the poor. The teaching of the Bible is that helping
the poor is something that people should do voluntarily. And yes, it
is undoubtedly true that most people do exaggerate their role in
acquiring their wealth. As a Christian I believe that everything I
have has been given to me by God. But I don’t see what this has to
do with the role of government.
One
final criticism of libertarianism concerns its belief that the free
market will somehow always act as a benevolent force. Most
libertarians believe that if the government would simply get out of
the way, the free market economy would naturally fix society’s
problems. This is naïve, both historically and theologically.
Historically, all that is needed is a quick glance at those moments
in our nation’s past when innovation outstripped regulation, such
as the early stages of the Industrial Revolution. When the free
market has no checks or balances, the strong tend to prey on the
weak.
At
this point, I would want to say that no, I do not believe that the
free market will somehow always act as a benevolent force, and I
suspect that there are very few libertarians that believe that if the
government would simply get out of the way, the free market economy
would naturally fix all society’s problems. However, I do think
that on balance, the free market does tend to work for the good of
society, and I think that there is plenty of empirical evidence which
shows that the free market is good for the poorest people in society.
And one could argue that the truly free market provides checks and
balances as effectively as most alternatives.
And so I might also be tempted to write “One final criticism of non-libertarians concerns their belief that government will somehow always act as a benevolent force. Most non-libertarians believe that if the government would simply act, it could fix society’s problems. This is naïve, both historically and theologically. Historically, what is needed is a detailed study of our nation’s past when innovation outstripped regulation to show how much the poor actually benefited.”
And so I might also be tempted to write “One final criticism of non-libertarians concerns their belief that government will somehow always act as a benevolent force. Most non-libertarians believe that if the government would simply act, it could fix society’s problems. This is naïve, both historically and theologically. Historically, what is needed is a detailed study of our nation’s past when innovation outstripped regulation to show how much the poor actually benefited.”
Theologically,
it is naïve to assume that individuals acting out of self-interest
will naturally create a society in which freedom increases. Sinful
greed and envy, which in practice play a major role in the free
market, cannot lead to sinless utopia. In other words, the free
market, for all of its benefits, is a medium of exchange for fallen
humanity. It excels other economic systems and often minimizes the
harm that our sin would otherwise cause. But as long as human beings
are the ones doing the exchanging, the free market will be to some
extent twisted and corrupted. As J. Budziszewski writes, “In the
marketplace our desires are aroused so insidiously and scratched so
efficiently that we spend our lives and fortunes just finding new
places where we might itch.”
OK
- so the free market will not lead to a sinless utopia. Who claimed
that it would? Theologically, it is naive to assume that state
intervention will do better.
Conclusion
Ideological
libertarianism latches on to the real value of individual freedom.
And as our government increases in scope and strength, appealing to a
less intrusive government will continue to find growing support. But
liberty is not God, and we tread on shaky ground when we treat it as
such. Liberty can only be true liberty when it is not our reigning
god. As Jesus said, “You will know the truth [about me], and the
truth will set you free” (John 8:32 ESV). We need not only freedom
from restrictions, but freedom for a life ordered toward Christ.
I
cannot find anything that I disagree with in Ashford’s conclusion.
But
my own conclusion is that it is difficult to see that anything that
he has said in this theological reflection on libertarianism actually
shows any significant problems with libertarianism, religious or
otherwise. I think that it is good and necessary for theologians to
subject ideologies, including political ideologies, to scrutiny.
Every ideology requires scrutiny, and I appreciate the fact that Mr
Ashford has written this article about libertarianism. But as a
Christian who is politically libertarian, I am not convinced that any
of the shots he has fired are on-target.
Postscript
Mr Ashford's article on libertarianism is one of a series of seven, beginning with "The (Religious) Problem with American Politics" and ending with "A (Religious) Alternative for American Politics". In between, he surveys the (religious) problems with liberalism, socialism, libertarianism, conservitivism and progressivism and nationalism.
On the whole, I like his approach. I think that the first and last articles are very good. The others are more a mixed bag, but contain a lot of good comments. In my opinion, the one on libertarianism is, by a considerable margin, the weakest. Since I write as a libertarian, it will not come as a surprise to Mr Ashford that I should say so. Indeed, in his opening article, he writes
Well, all I can say is that I think that what I have said in my response will stand up to examination. As a cynical character in C.S. Lewis' book The Pilgrim's Regress says: "What is the response to an argument turning on the belief that two and two makes four? The answer is 'You say that because you are a mathematician." Just because I happen to be a libertarian does not mean that I am wrong in my assessment.
My final comment is that I think that part of the problem is that Bruce Ashford, like a lot of observers, doesn't really understand libertarianism as fully as he might. Libertarianism revolves around not just the importance of freedom, but also around the non-aggression principle and the rejection of force and violence - a point that Tom Woods makes very effectively in his response to Ashford, which is why Woods' response is a necessary supplement to mine.
Postscript
Mr Ashford's article on libertarianism is one of a series of seven, beginning with "The (Religious) Problem with American Politics" and ending with "A (Religious) Alternative for American Politics". In between, he surveys the (religious) problems with liberalism, socialism, libertarianism, conservitivism and progressivism and nationalism.
On the whole, I like his approach. I think that the first and last articles are very good. The others are more a mixed bag, but contain a lot of good comments. In my opinion, the one on libertarianism is, by a considerable margin, the weakest. Since I write as a libertarian, it will not come as a surprise to Mr Ashford that I should say so. Indeed, in his opening article, he writes
“The great problem with a project like this, of course, is that we always have a keen eye to see the idolatry operative in other ideologies. Conservatives spot the idolatry of socialism quickly, and vice versa. But as Christians, we must have the humility to recognize that we all are “prone to wander,” that our view of politics may be much more idolatrous than we have yet to realize. May God grant us the courage to discern and oppose idolatry wherever it is found, beginning in our own hearts, our own churches, and our own preferred political parties and ideologies.”So, obviously, it will be said "You say that because you are a libertarian".
Well, all I can say is that I think that what I have said in my response will stand up to examination. As a cynical character in C.S. Lewis' book The Pilgrim's Regress says: "What is the response to an argument turning on the belief that two and two makes four? The answer is 'You say that because you are a mathematician." Just because I happen to be a libertarian does not mean that I am wrong in my assessment.
My final comment is that I think that part of the problem is that Bruce Ashford, like a lot of observers, doesn't really understand libertarianism as fully as he might. Libertarianism revolves around not just the importance of freedom, but also around the non-aggression principle and the rejection of force and violence - a point that Tom Woods makes very effectively in his response to Ashford, which is why Woods' response is a necessary supplement to mine.
4 comments:
I think your response is measured and convincing. Ashford's position may serve as a warning to libertarians as to possible pitfalls they need to avoid but, like you, I think his stance lacks the necessary nuance in places.
What he would benefit in saying is that libertarians need to remember their stance for liberty and justice is grounded in God.
Your critique would benefit in noting the idolatry that Ashford warns us of is also present for the statist position. There may be the danger that the individualist libertarian is tempted by the idolatry of self and desires freedom from God's law; but those who look to the state also face this problem. Not to mention those who would be our rulers. If anything, Scripture warns us far more concerning the state idol (think Revelation). Ashford treats the state as far more neutral than what it is.
I would argue that the Christian libertarian position is in part a response to the Fall. We can't trust fallen individuals seeking their own liberty (anarchy) but nor can we trust fallen leaders who would become as gods over us (statism). The solution is to restrict the anarchist tendencies by having laws enforcing respect of person and property, and restrict the statist tendencies by limiting laws to respect of person and property; that is, libertarianism.
Thanks for those excellent points, bethyada.
A very enjoyable blog post, thanks. Can I ask whereabouts in the UK you are? Christian libertarianism seems to be almost non-existent over here, it's encouraging to see a like-minded soul!
I'm in the North of Scotland.
Post a Comment